Karl Rosenkranz's 'Life of Hegel' 4/24 - The early Philosophy of Mind
(The article below is reproduced at hegel.net with the kind permission of its author, Stephen Cowley . It first appeared 1-2/2012 on the hegel.net Hegel mailing list and was then published 6/2012 as article with the pictures below on his blog ‘Hegelian News & Reviews’ )
Book One Chapter 19 (continued) Philosophy of Mind
I have already broken my summary of this chapter up into three and
this last part on mind could itself be broken up. Rosenkranz is here
discussing the text known to us as
System of Ethical Life
.
According to Osmo, this dates from 1802-03 and Rosenkranz has misdated
it. Hegel develops the concept of ethical life (
Sittlichkeit
)
here, which he later did under the name of Natural Law. He neglects
anthropology and psychology, ending with brief treatments of art and
religion. The notion of ethical life is intended to be concrete and that
from which abstract law and morality are lifted. This is implicitly a
critique of the lifeless ethics of Kant and the impractical politics of
Fichte. Yet, says Rosenkranz, he is still relatively Platonic.
Ethical Life
Hegel begins with the idea that the universal and particular must be posited as identical in absolute ethical life, whilst being different in themselves. He calls the universal Intuition and the particular Concept. The ideas developed are structured differently from the later Philosophy of Mind, but are still recognisable. There is:
- Ethical Life as relationship (work, property, family)
- The Negative (conscience, crime and retribution)
- Absolute Ethical Life (the people, classes, constitutional government)
This is a little different from the
Philosophy of Right
,
where family is at the start of part three rather than the end of part
one. I wonder if Hegel’s first idea was not the best.
Ethical life as relationship sees categories develop through interaction
with nature and other people’s wishes to the point where public
institutions emerge. This involves negation, which includes
confrontation and differentiation until the absolute emerges as a
resolution, i.e. giving each its due in a greater whole which may be
logically divided. The absolutely ethical takes the form of legislation.
Hegel relates government to needs, justice and education. Here
Rosenkranz reproduces the text of Hegel, but with a lot of condensation
and interpretation.Under the heading of Need, he thinks inequality
should be moderated. Under Justice, he discusses constitutions, civil
and criminal law, legal developments and war.
Religion
In a final part of the
System of Ethical Life
that is now
lost, Hegel discusses philosophy, religion and art as expressions of a
national spirit, but in such general terms that it is hard to see if
Greece, Israel or modern Europe is meant. Rosenkranz discusses the
sections on religion. This takes three forms, which Hegel borrows from
the philosophy of nature:
- Natural Religion
- Difference and reconciliation
- Christianity
Religious consciousness contains both the speculative Idea and the
empirical psychology of a people, whose living God is here present.
Sacrifice moves from thought to deed. Hegel says:
“This deed, the irony with regard to the perishable and useful deeds of man, is reconciliation, the fundamental idea of religion.”
Natural religion seems to appear first, but soon Rome chased the
independent life out of individual peoples. Natural religion is
Pantheist – it sees nature itself as sacred and we find our life with
the Gods expressed in a beautiful mythology.
Secondly though, this becomes a memory, for the unity of mind and its
reality is broken. Rome destroyed the original individuality of peoples.
Reconciliation is thus sought in universality and the original identity
re-emerges in the Heavens.
Thirdly, the absolute confidence of Christ in reconciliation became the
foundation of a universal religion, originating in the most chastened of
peoples, for the depth of their pain gave his voice a truth that
everyone could hear. His assurance combined with mistrust led to his
death. Nature being emptied of divinity, only Christ was divine. The
Cross of the universal state symbolises the mistrust of the world. Hegel
wrote:
“The thought that God himself had died on earth only serves to express the feeling of this infinite pain; the same as the fact that he rose from the tomb expresses its reconciliation.”
Religion must thus evoke the pain to allow the reconciliation:
“The ancient curse that weighs on everything is broken. All of nature finds mercy and its pain is salved.”
Natural religion expressed itself through art in mythology. Christianity expresses itself in ideas, e.g. the Trinity. Reconciliation expresses itself in the idea of Love, which divinises the mother of God. In Catholicism, this religion becomes beautiful. The poetry of consecration is suppressed in Protestantism, which has imprinted on religion an overall character of subjectivity. It transposes religion into a key of nostalgia and turns its attention to everyday life. Rosenkranz notes that Hegel did not, as several did at this time, convert to Catholicism, though he saw Protestantism as simply another finite form alongside it. Rather he thought that a third form of Christianity was possible by the mediation of philosophy. Rosenkranz cites him as saying:
“One can neither revive nor maim that passed beauty, but simply recognise the necessity of its disappearance as presaging something better to take its place. Thus far, nature is reconciled, but remains in itself something profane.”
He imagines that a free people may reflectively grasp a truer form of
sanctifying spirit and that this is the task of philosophy. Which sounds
overly ambitious to me.
Chapter 20 Death of Father and Exit from the Shadows
Hegel heard that his father had died through a letter from his sister
Christiane. He inherited 3,154 florins. A passport – for Germany was not
then united – describes him as five feet two inches, but Rosenkranz says
that feet were not standardised at that time in Germany. The lack of
standard measures reminds me of the economic underdevelopment of
Germany. The French had implemented the metric system around this time,
for example. I had always imagined Hegel as quite tall in an average
sort of way, perhaps because he seems to look down from the portraits of
him. His hair was brown and his eyes were grey.
Hegel prepares to go to Jena and writes to Schelling on 2 November 1800.
This is the famous letter where he says he is interested in Bamberg but
is looking for a good beer. He adds that this is for his health and that
he would also like to visit a Catholic town to see the religion up
close. He intends to devote himself to studies that that he has already
begun before the literary whirlwind of Jena. He is also concerned about
the cost of living. He remarks finally that he is considering how to
return from science to the life of men and sees Schelling as an
admirable model for this. I can’t help but think there is maybe an echo
of Plato’s cave in that.
Impressions and replies so far
Rosenkranz’s book has a kind of spiral structure as he addresses
Hegel’s views on religion, politics, etc at different stages of his
life. Hence I am moving on rather than hoping to resolve any issues that
have come up in discussion at this stage, on the grounds that more of
Rosenkranz will perhaps shed as much light as my going over my initial
impressions. Rosenkranz is offering a ladder from “ordinary
consciousness” to the Hegelian system, a kind of more accessible version
of what the
Phenomenology
advertises itself as, but does not
always live up to, owing to its abstruse structure and forms of
expression.
Despite that, two final remarks that relate to recent comments [on the
Hegel mailing lists] are, firstly, that I still think there was a period
in the 1790s when Kant addressed religion with all the force of his
Pietist background and the authority of his years (and before one could
say he was senile or his powers were significantly declining) and when
Hegel was still impressed with and trying to rethink fairly superficial
(basically Enlightenment) versions of Christianity, where Kant’s views
have a greater insight than Hegel’s. Secondly, on matters of church and
state, there are considerable ambiguities in both terms (the state is
conceived as operating through legal sanctions, but the content of the
law can be quite various in its religious implications, for example)
that justify a more historical approach to differentiating them. Hence
Hegel’s later ideas, when he had read more, are likely to be more
interesting. (Incidentally, I’m not familiar with the idea of the church
as being itself a sacrament, though I think this relates to what Hegel
shortly says on Catholicism as embodying an idea of beauty.)